A role of environmental ethics in modern society - Экология - Скачать бесплатно
Kyiv national university of culture and arts
REFERAT
“ A role of the Environmental Ethics in the modern society”
Executed by: student TBA-40 group
Faculty: direction and
television
Radchenko Nataliya
Controlled by: Karpenko
Valeriy I.
KYIV-2000
A Role of the Environmental Ethics in the modern society.
The inspiration for environmental ethics was the first Earth Day in
1970 when environmentalists started urging philosophers who were involved
with environmental groups to do something about environmental ethics. An
intellectual climate had developed in the last few years of the 1960s in
large part because of the publication of two papers in Science: Lynn
White`s “The Historical Roots of our Ecological Crisis” (March 1967) and
Garett Hardin`s "The Tragedy of the Commons" (December 1968). Most
influential with regard to this kind of thinking, however, was an essay in
Aldo Leopold`s A Sand County Almanac, "The Land Ethic," in which Leopold
explicitly claimed that the roots of the ecological crisis were
philosophical. Although originally published in 1949, Sand County Almanac
became widely available in 1970 in a special Sierra Club/Ballantine
edition, which included essays from a second book, Round River.
Most academic activity in the 1970s was spent debating the Lynn White
thesis and the tragedy of the commons. These debates were primarily
historical, theological, and religious, not philosophical. Throughout most
of the decade philosophers sat on the sidelines trying to determine what a
field called environmental ethics might look like. The first philosophical
conference was organized by William Blackstone at the University of Georgia
in 1972. The proceedings were published as Philosophy and Environmental
Crisis in 1974, which included Pete Gunter`s first paper on the Big
Thicket. In 1972 a book called “Is It Too Late?” A Theology of Ecology,
written by John B. Cobb, was published. It was the first single-authored
book written by a philosopher, even though the primary focus of the book
was theological and religious. In 1973 an Australian philosopher, Richard
Routley (now Sylvan), presented a paper at the 15th World Congress of
Philosophy "Is There a Need for a New, an Environmental, Ethic?" A year
later John Passmore, another Australian, wrote Man’s Responsibility for
Nature, in which, reacting to Routley, he argued that there was no need for
an environmental ethic at all. Most debates among philosophers until the
mid-1980s was focused on refuting Passmore. In 1975 environmental ethics
came to the attention of mainstream philosophy with the publication of
Holmes Rolston, III`s paper, "Is There an Ecological Ethic?" in Ethics.
Arne Naess, a Norwegian philosopher and the founding editor of the
journal Inquiry authored and published a paper in Inquiry “The Shallow and
the Deep, Long-range Ecology Movement” in 1973, which was the beginning of
the deep ecology movement. Important writers in this movement include
George Sessions, Bill DeVall, Warwick Fox, and, in some respects, Max
Oelschlaeger.
Throughout the 1970s Inquiry was the primary philosophy journal that
dealt with environmental ethics. Environmental ethics was, for the most
part, considered a curiosity and mainstream philosophy journals rarely
published more than one article per year, if that. Opportunities for
publishing dramatically improved in 1979 when Eugene C. Hargrove founded
the journal Environmental Ethics. The name of the journal became the name
of the field.
The first five years of the journal was spent mostly arguing about
rights for nature and the relationship of environmental ethics and animal
rights/animal liberation. Rights lost and animal welfare ethics was
determined to be a separate field. Animal rights has since developed as a
separate field with a separate journal, first, Ethics and Animals, which
was later superseded by Between the Species.
Cobb published another book in the early 1980s, The Liberation of Life
with co-author Charles Birch. This book took a process philosophy approach
in accordance with the philosophy of organism of Alfred North Whitehead.
Robin Attfield, a philosopher in Wales, wrote a book called The Ethics of
Environmental Concern. It was the first full-length response to Passmore.
An anthology of papers, Ethics and the Environment, was edited by Donald
Scherer and Tom Attig.
There was a turning point about 1988 when many single-authored books
began to come available: Paul Taylor`s Respect for Nature; Holmes Rolston`s
Environmental Ethics; Mark Sagoff`s The Economy of the Earth; and Eugene C.
Hargrove`s Foundations of Environmental Ethics. J. Baird Callicott created
a collection of his papers, In Defence of the Land Ethic. Bryan Norton
wrote Why Preserve Natural Diversity? followed more recently by Toward
Unity among Environmentalists. A large number of books have been written by
Kristin Shrader-Frechette on economics and policy.
In the 1980s a second movement, ecofeminism, developed. Karen Warren
is the key philosopher, although the ecofeminism movement involves many
thinkers from other fields. It was then followed by a third, social
ecology, based on the views of Murray Bookchin. An important link between
academics and radical environmentalists was established with the creation
of the Canadian deep ecology journal, The Trumpeter. In 1989, Earth Ethics
Quarterly was begun as a more popular environmental publication. Originally
intended primarily as a reprint publication, now as a publication of the
Centre for Respect for Life and Environment, it is focused more on
international sustainable development.
The 1990s began with the establishment of the International Society
for Environmental Ethics, which was founded largely through the efforts of
Laura Westra and Holmes Rolston, III. It now has members throughout the
world. In 1992, a second refereed philosophy journal, dedicated to
environmental ethics, Environmental Values published its first issue in
England.
On the theoretical level, Taylor and Rolston, despite many
disagreements, can be regarded as objective nonanthropocentric intrinsic
value theorists. Callicott, who follows Aldo Leopold closely, is a
subjective nonanthropocentric intrinsic value theorist. Hargrove is
considered a weak anthropocentric intrinsic value theorist. Sagoff is very
close to this position although he doesn’t talk about intrinsic value much
and takes a Kantian rather than an Aristotlian approach. At the far end is
Bryan Norton who thought up weak anthropocentrism but wants to replace
intrinsic value with a pragmatic conception of value.
A brief history of environmental consciousness in the western world
places our views in perspective and provides a context for understanding
the maze of related and unrelated thoughts, philosophies, and practices
that we call "environmentalism." Understanding where the questions being
asked and analyzed are coming from is essential in environmental analysis:
the kinds of questions asked by an environmental group and their
interpretation of the results can be vastly different from, for example, a
utility, logging company or special interest (ranchers grazing public
lands, and so forth).
The term "environmental ethics," in fact the whole field, is a very
recent phenomenum, actually only several decades old, although many
particular concerns or philosophical threads have been developing for
several centuries. A Professor named Eugene Hargroves began a journal he
named Environmental Ethics in the late 1970s in which controversies
regarding environmental behaviour and visions could be discussed. This name
became an umbrella for a group of strange bedfellows. A controversy had
begun in 1974 when an Australian named John Passmore published a book
called "Man`s responsibility for nature: ecological problems and western
traditions" in which he argued that environmental preservation and concern
was inconsistent with western tradition. Robin Attfield replied 1983 in a
book entitled "The ethics of environmental concern" by holding that the
stewardship tradition was more important than dominion in western thought,
and that this is what forms the foundation for environmental ethics.
Environmental ethics is a collection of independent ethical
generalizations, not a tight, rationally ordered set of rules.
Environmental ethics will be a compilation of interrelated independent
guidelines - a process field that will be coming together for a long time.
Ethics really flow from peoples perceptions, attitudes and behaviour -
as in the case of environmental ethics and animal liberation. Like chess,
decision making in life is very perceptual or intuitive - by analogy, there
are l) favourite formations (of players or arguments); 2) empirical
investigation of these (with maximum and minimum expectations); which leads
to a progressive deepening of perspective.
The problem is only dimly perceived in the beginning, but becomes
clearer with thought and re-examination. What holds a chess game together
is not the rules but the experience the individual player. A grand master
at chess sees more on a chessboard in a few seconds than an average player
sees in thirty minutes.
Environmental ethics today encompasses a diverse, not necessarily related,
anthology including:
1. Animal rights.
2. The Land Ethic.
3. Ecofeminism.
4. Deep Ecology.
5. Shallow Ecology.
6. The rights of rocks, and so forth.
8. Bioethics.
Bioethics could be defined as the study of ethical issues and decision-
making associated with the use of living organisms and medicine. It
includes both medical ethics and environmental ethics. Rather than defining
a correct decision it is about the process of decision-making balancing
different benefits, risks and duties. The word "bioethics" was first used
in 1970, however, the concept of bioethics is much older, as we can see in
the ethics formulated and debated in literature, art, music and the general
cultural and religious traditions of our ancestors.
Society is facing many important decisions about the use of science
and technology. These decisions affect the environment, human health,
society and international policy. To resolve these issues, and develop
principles to help us make decisions we need to involve anthropology,
sociology, biology, medicine, religion, psychology, philosophy, and
economics; we must combine the scientific rigour of biological data, with
the values of religion and philosophy to develop a world-view. Bioethics is
therefore challenged to be a multi-sided and thoughtful approach to
decision-making so that it may be relevant to all aspects of human life.
The term bioethics reminds us of the combination of biology and ethics,
topics that are intertwined. New technology can be a catalyst for our
thinking about issues of life, and we can think of the examples like
assisted reproductive technologies, life sustaining technology, organ
transplantation, and genetics, which have been stimuli for research into
bioethics in the last few decades. Another stimulus has been the
environmental problems.
There are large and small problems in ethics. We can think of problems
that involve the whole world, and problems which involve a single person.
We can think of global problems, such as the depletion of the ozone layer
which is increasing UV radiation affecting all living organisms. This
problem could be solved by individual action to stop using ozone-depleting
chemicals, if alternatives are available to consumers. However, global
action was taken to control the problem. The international convention to
stop the production of many ozone-depleting chemicals is one of the best
examples yet of applying universal environmental ethics.
Another problem is greenhouse warming, which results mainly from
energy use. This problem however can only be solved by individual action to
reduce energy use, because we cannot easily ban the use of energy. We could
do this by turning off lights, turning down heaters and air conditioners,
building more energy efficient buildings, shutting doors, and driving with
a light foot. These are all simple actions which everyone must do if we are
concerned about our planet, yet not many do so. Energy consumption could be
reduced 50-80% by lifestyle change with current technology if people wanted
to. New technology may help, but lifestyle change can have much more
immediate affect.
Environmental ethics is a relatively new field - and the name
"environmental ethics" derives from Eugene Hargrove`s journal, which was
begun in late 1970s.
This field - environmental ethics, - will be subsumed as other areas
of applied ethics develop more fully. The early pieces or threads of
environmental ethics were disconnected...one needs a quick review to fully
comprehend today`s "whole" - and know the directions in which the threads
lead.
Environmental ethicists as well as policy-makers, activists etc.
frequently speak about the need for preservation of various parts of
nature. Two main grounds are repeatedly presented for this need:
1. Our moral responsibilities to future human beings (sometimes called
sustainable development) require that we stop using technology and science
for short-term gains at the expense of long-term risks of very negative
ecological effects for future people. In several official declarations and
policy-documents this idea has been expressed as "the precautionary
principle", roughly the idea that we should not use particular means of
production, distribution etc. unless they have been shown not to effect too
serious risks. However, it is far from clear what is meant by this. What
determines whether or not the effecting of a certain risk (in order to
secure some short-term gain) is too serious or not? - and what determines
whether or not this has been "shown"? Some traditional decision-theorists
would say that it is a question of traditional instrumental efficiency
(i.e. rationality) in relation to morally respectable aims. Some ethicists
would instead claim that it is a question of whether or not the severity of
the scenario illustrating an actualization of the risk in question makes
the taking of this risk morally wrong in itself. Others, yet, hint that
they want to take a stand in between these two extremes, however, without
specifying what this could mean. There is also a rather grim debate
regarding whether or not it can ever be shown that a certain action does
not effect too serious risks, and this of course depends on what
requirements should be laid on someone who purports to show such a thing.
In both cases, the questions seem to boil down to basic issues regarding
what is required of risky decisions in order to make them morally
justified. But, obviously, it must be a kind of moral justification
different from the one dealt with by traditional ethical theories of the
rights and wrongs of actions, since these only deal with justification in
terms of actual outcomes, not in terms of risks for such outcomes.
2. Natural systems possess a value in themselves which makes them worth
preserving also at the expense of human well-being and man-made constructs.
This idea is less common in official documents than the former (although it
is explicitely set out as a part of the basis of the Swedish Environmental
Policy Act) than it is among environmental philosophers and ethicists.
However, also this idea is far from clear, since it is not clear neither
how a natural system is to be distinguished from a non-natural one and why
this difference is to be taken as morally relevant, nor why preservation is
the only recommendation which follows from the placing of an intrinsic
value in nature. Although there are several suggestion on what it is that
makes certain systems intrinsically valuable, it is has not been
sufficiently explained, first, why these characteristics (typically
complexity, self-preservation/replication, beauty etc.) do not justify
preservation also of systems normally not taken to be natural (such as
metropolitan areas, hamburger restaurants or nuclear power-plants),
secondly, why this value does not imply a recommendation to reshape rather
than preserve natural systems, in order to increase the presence and
magnitude of the value-making characteristics. In particular, it seems to
be a challenge for a preservationist to argue in favour of restoration of
certain biotic variants, without leaving the door open also for reshaping,
for example by the use of modern biotechnology.
The aim of this research-project is to attack these two families of issues,
both connected to the justification of common ideas regarding the
importance of preserving various parts of nature. In one part (carried out
by christian menthe), the project will be aimed at mapping out moral
intuitions regarding the moral responsibility of the taking of risks, in
order to use these for developing a normative theory of the morality of
risk-taking which can be used to underpin a more specific version of the
precautionary principle. The other part of the project is instead aimed at
systematically reviewing various proposals (and new home-made to how to
distinguish between that (i.e. nature)) which should typically be preserved
according to preservationists and that which does not need to be so
preserved, and to resist the conclusion that reshaping of nature might be a
better idea from the point of view of typically preservationist values than
actual preservation. The focus here will be on ideas ascribing a value in
itself to nature or certain natural systems.
Bibliography list.
1. Charles Birch and John B. Cobb, Jr., The Liberation of Life: From the
Cell to the Community (Denton, Tex.: Environmental Ethics
Books, 1990), 357 pages.
2. Yrjo Sepanmaa, The Beauty of Environment: A General Model for
Environmental Aesthetics, 2d ed. (Denton, Tex.: Environmental Ethics
Books, 1993), 191 pages.
3. John B. Cobb, Jr., Is It Too Late? A Theology of Ecology, rev. ed.
(Denton, Tex.: Environmental Ethics Books, 1995), 112 pages.
4. Eugene C. Hargrove, Foundations of Environmental Ethics (reprint ed.,
Denton, Tex.: Environmental Ethics Books, 1996), 229 pages.
5. Robin Attfield, The Ethics of Environmental Concern (Denton, Tex.:
Environmental Ethics Books, 1983), 237 pages.
|